675648c2785e9a3
حکمت معاصر

نوع مقاله : علمی-پژوهشی

نویسنده

استادیار فلسفه، دانشگاه صنعتی امیرکبیر (پلی‌تکنیک تهران)،

چکیده

روش پژوهش فلسفی را می‌توان به انحاء گوناگونی طبقه‌بندی کرد. حسب چگونگی رابطه با گذشته عرصه فلسفه، این مقاله دو سبک فلسفه‌ورزی را از یکدیگر متمایز می‌سازد: «روزآمد» و «تاریخی». وفاداران به سبک فلسفه‌ورزی روزآمد، عمل حرفه‌ای خود را مستقل از تاریخ فلسفه دانسته و برای مواجهه با چالش‌‌های فکری امروزین تنها بر خردورزی حال‌محور خویش اتکا می‌نمایند. فلسفه تحلیلی در دوران معاصر نمونه ممثّل این رویکرد است که بسیاری از پیشگامان آن، تاریخ فلسفه را به دیده حقارت می‌نگرند. پایبندان به سبک فلسفه‌ورزی تاریخی، در مقابل، برای نیل به حقیقت به گذشته فلسفه رجوع نموده و فلسفه‌ی خود را در دادوستد فکری با آن شکل می‌دهند. تحقق این سبک را می‌توان میان فیلسوفان اسلامی رهگیری کرد که خود را نوعاً در امتداد عقبه‌ای از اندیشمندان گذشته می‌شناسانند. سبک اتخاذشده از سوی وفاداران به هریک از این دو اسلوب اثرات تعیین‌کننده‌ای بر نحوه آموزش و آموختن، شیوه و حتی ادبیات نگارش و همچنین تاریخ‌نگاری فلسفه توسط آنان دارد. این مقاله به مشخصه‌یابی هریک از دو سبک یادشده و برشمردن استلزامات آنها پرداخته و در پایان آن دو را در هم‌سنجی با یکدیگر قرار می‌دهد.

کلیدواژه‌ها

عنوان مقاله [English]

Two Kinds of Philosophizing with Respect to Philosophy’s Past

نویسنده [English]

  • mehdi golparvar rouzbahani

Assistant Professor of Philosophy Department of Humanities and Islamic Studies Amirkabir University of Technology (Tehran Polytechnic) Tehran, IRAN

چکیده [English]

Abstract.
Willard Van Orman Quine, one of the dominant figures in the 20th-century Anglo-American philosophy, is said to have joked that “there are two sorts of people interested in philosophy, those interested in philosophy and those interested in the history of philosophy”. Quine seems to suggest, in a humorous manner, that the history of philosophy lies completely out of the realm of real philosophy. If taken seriously, philosophy would have nothing to do with the history of philosophy. I argue in this article that Professor Quine and others of his mindset are wrong in that they mix up things that should be discriminated.
As is well known, attitudes toward philosophy may be categorized in a variety of ways, among them is the familiar division of schools of “Analytic” and “Continental” in the Western philosophy, and the schools of “Peripatetic”, “Illuminationist” and “Transcendental” in the Islamic tradition of philosophy. In the same line of drawing contrast between different modes of philosophical thought and according to their relation with the history of the enterprise of philosophy, this article differentiates between two kinds of philosophizing, namely “trendy” and “historical”.
Those loyal to the trendy way of philosophizing see their professional practice as independent from philosophy’s past, and rely solely on the ability of their “presentist” reason to address the currently existing challenges. This may be called a memoryless way of philosophizing, as there would be no need from this outlook to be concerned with philosophy’s past or to keep a memory of what has already happened in the enterprise. Philosophy as expected to be practiced now may be said to be detached from philosophy’s past, just as is the case in sciences. Those people who may be interested in the historical issues may of course refer to the history of philosophy, but this would not be philosophy proper. One could regard the contemporary Analytic philosophy which is the mainstream in Anglo-American circles as an exemplar of this attitude, whose pioneers give a demeaning look at the history of philosophy. As Wittgenstein has put in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, “most of the propositions and questions to be found in philosophical works are not false but nonsensical.” If this is the case, why should philosophers bother themselves with the history of philosophy at all?
Adherents of the historical way of philosophizing, on contrary, turn to philosophy’s past seeking philosophical truth, and shape their philosophy in exchange with it. According to this outlook, history of philosophy is like a precious mine of problems and ideas that were explored partially by some brilliant minds in the past. We may take benefit of their efforts by taking their philosophical concerns serious and move forward the enterprise by engaging with their problems and ideas. Many updates from different aspects would be needed for sure, but the essence of philosophical problems remains the same through the history of ideas. We would therefore need to do philosophy historically, that is to master the past as the key to understand the present. This type of philosophizing seems to have been realized by Islamic philosophers, who typically position themselves within a lineage of preceding thinkers. Just take the example of Mulla Sadra’s Asfar, a masterpiece in transcendental school of Islamic philosophy, and see the vast amount of discussions devoted to the thought of past thinkers.
The way of philosophizing adopted by the advocates of each camp would have crucial impacts on their philosophy’s pedagogy and writing style, as well as on their historiography of philosophy. Especially, both are very susceptible to historical anachronism, namely to shape a distorted narrative of the past as viewed from the supposed vantage point of the present. Moreover, each attitude has also its peculiar characteristics. On one hand we see that the writings of trendy philosophers are typically overwhelmed with philosophical jargon; i.e., expressions that have gained very specialist and narrow meanings. On the other hand, the relations of ideas explored by historical philosophers and their development over centuries are usually very complicated to be captured, so the need for long years, even decades, for a scholar to be able to enter the circle of interlocutors.
The present article characterizes trendy and historical ways of philosophizing separately, details their implications, and finally put them in comparison against each other. This problem falls within the scope of what is usually called metaphilosophy, and would make salient some features in the enterprise of philosophy that otherwise would have remained obscure. Another metaphilosophical issue is the probable unnoticed effects of the history of philosophy on the work of philosophers, whether trendies or historicals. This issue remains to be investigated further in a subsequent research.

کلیدواژه‌ها [English]

  • Analytic Philosophy
  • historical philosophizing
  • history of philosophy
  • Islamic philosophy
  • metaphilosophy
رحمانی، منصوره، احد فرامرز قراملکی، و قاسم کاکایی (1396). «انگاره ملاصدرا از فلسفه»، خردنامه صدرا، دوره 22، شماره 4 (پیاپی 88)، صص 61-74.
طباطبایی، محمدحسین (1390). اصول فلسفه و روش رئالیسم، مقدمه و پاورقی: مرتضی مطهری، ج 1، تهران: صدرا.
گل‌پرور روزبهانی، مهدی (1396). «سبک‌شناسی رویکردهای تاریخی به فلسفه اسلامی»، روش‌شناسی علوم انسانی، دوره 23، شماره 93، صص 185-207.
مطهری، مرتضی (1352). «نگاهی اجمالی به سیر فلسفه در اسلام»، مقالات و بررسیها، شماره 13–16، صص 82–99.
Adamson, Peter (2002). The Arabic Plotinus: A Philosophical Study of the ‘Theology of Aristotle’, London: Duckworth.
Carr, E. H. (1990 [1961]). What Is History?, Second edition, Edited by R. W. Davies, Penguin Books.
Fischer, David Hackett (1970). Historians’ Fallacies: Towards a Logic of Historical Thought, New York: Harper and Row.
Gerson, Lloyd P. (2006). “Platonic Knowledge and the Standard Analysis”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies 14: 455–74.
Glock, Hans-Johann (2008), What is Analytic Philosophy?, Cambridge University Press.
Hadot, Pierre (1981). Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique, Paris: Etudes augustiniennes.
Hadot, Pierre (1995). Qu'est-ce que la philosophie antique?, Paris: Gallimard.
Hare, Peter (ed.) (1988). Doing Philosophy Historically, Buffalo: Prometheus.
Kremer, Michael (2013). “What Is the Good of Philosophical History?” in Reck (2013), pp. 294–325.
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1984). “The Relationship of Philosophy to its Past,” in Philosophy in History, ed. Richard Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 31–48.
O’Hear, Anthony (ed.) (2009). Conceptions of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press.
Overgaard, Søren, Paul Gilbert, and Stephen Burwood (2013). An Introduction to Metaphilosophy, Cambridge University Press.
Piercey, Robert (2009). The Uses of the Past From Heidegger to Rorty: Doing Philosophy Historically, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Ragland, C.P. and Sarah Heidt (ed.) (2001), What Is Philosophy?, Yale University Press.
Reck, Erich H. (ed.) (2013). The Historical Turn in Analytic Philosophy, Palgrave MacMillan.
Rorty, Richard (2007). “Analytic and conversational philosophy”, in his Philosophy as Cultural Politics: Philosophical. Papers, Volume 4, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 120–130.
Soames, Scott (2003). Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, 2 vols., Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Soames, Scott (2006a). “Précis of Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1, The Dawn of Analysis”, Philosophical Studies 129: 605–608.
Soames, Scott (2006b). “What is history for? Reply to critics of The Dawn of Analysis”, Philosophical Studies 129: 645–665.
Soames, Scott (2007). “What we know now that we didn’t know then: reply to critics of The Age of Meaning”, Philosophical Studies 135: 461–478.
Sorell, Tom & Rogers, G. A. J. (eds.) (2005). Analytic Philosophy and History of Philosophy, Oxford University Press.
Strauss, Leo (2013 [1935]). Philosophie und Gesetz in Gesammelte Schriften, Band 2, Heinrich Meier (ed.), Zweite Auflage, Stuttgart & Weimar: J. B. Metzler.
Vahid, Hamid (2019). “The dispositional architecture of epistemic reasons”, Philosophical Studies 176, 1887–1904. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1102-y
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1963 [1961]). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, The German Text with English Translation by D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.