Document Type : Biannual Journal

Authors

1 Hakim sabzevari University, sabzevar, Iran

2 Department of Islamic theachings, Neyshabur University of Medical Sciences, Neyshabur, Iran, momenim@nums.ac.ir (Corsponding outhor)

Abstract

Logicians, such as Avicenna (or Ibn Sīnā), give moral propositions (like “injustice is bad” and “justice is good”) as examples of “popular” (mashhūrāt) propositions and praised opinions in the section of dialectics. However, Islamic theologians (those adhering to justice or ‘adliyya) cite these propositions in their discussion of rational goodness and badness. This can be discussed in different respects: Are goodness and badness propositions primitively self-evident propositions or just popular propositions? Are they rational or legislated propositions? Do they admit of truth and falsity? Are they realistic or irrealistic? If they are popular propositions, then can their goodness or badness still be essential? In this paper, we are concerned with this latter question. To begin with, according to passages from Avicenna, these propositions are admittedly popular, but then the question arises of whether this is compatible with their goodness and badness being essential. This is because the essentiality of goodness and badness implies their reality, whereas a merely popular proposition does not have a reality beyond an agreement among rational agents. In the first case, popularity or general interests are at stake, whereas essentiality amounts to being detached from general interests or popularity within the society, in the sense that an act is immediately described as good or bad, but this is at odds with what logicians have suggested. The question of this research is to reveal a conflict between essentiality and rationality of such propositions on the one hand, and their popularity, on the other. We begin with an introduction of epistemological and ontological dimensions of the problem, and then consider the problem in terms of logic, referring to passages from Avicenna in this regard, and after an elucidation of the conflict, we finally formulate Muẓaffar’s solution to the conflict. The idea is that although the popularity of such propositions is incompatible with essentiality or rationality of good and badness as widely understood by theologians, a more refined understanding of essentiality and rationality will help resolve the conflict.

Keywords

 
Avicenna. 1400. Al-rasā’il (The essays). Qom: Bidar. [In Arabic]
Avicenna. 1404. Al-shifā’, kitāb al-burhān (The book of healing, section of proofs). Qom: Library of Ayatollah Mar‘ashi Najaf. [In Arabic]
Avicenna. 1404. Al-shifā’, kitāb al-jadal (The book of healing, section of dialectics). Qom: Library of Ayatollah Mar‘ashi Najaf. [In Arabic]
Avicenna. 1404. Al-shifā’, kitāb al-khiṭāba (The book of healing, section of rhetorics). Qom: Library of Ayatollah Mar‘ashi Najaf. [In Arabic]
Avicenna. 1405. Manṭiq al-mashriqiyyīn (Logics of orientals). Qom: Library of Ayatollah Mar‘ashi Najafi. [In Arabic]
Avicenna. 1379. Al-najāt. Edited by Muhammad Taqi Danishpazhuh. Tehran: University of Tehran. [In Arabic]
Avicenna. 1376. Ilāhiyyāt al-shifā’ (Theology from the book of healing). Edited by Hasan Hasanzada Amuli. Qom: Islamic Propagation Office. [In Arabic]
Ibn Nūbakht. 1413. Al-yāqūt fī ‘ilm al-kalām (The ruby in the science of theology). Edited by ‘Ali Akbar Ziya’i. First edition. Qom: Library of Ayatollah Mar‘ashi Najafi. [In Arabic]
Jurjānī, Alī ibn Muḥammad. 1429. Sharḥ al-mawāqif (Exposition of the stations). N.p.: Dar al-Basa’ir. [In Arabic]
Al-Ḥillī. 1413. Kashf al-murād fī sharḥ tajrīd al-i‘tiqād (Discovery of the intent in exposition of the purification of the belief). Edited by Hasan Hasanzada Amuli. Qom: Mu’assisat al-Nashr al-Islami. [In Arabic]
Al-Ḥillī. 1371. Al-jawhar al-naḍīd (Accumulated jewelry). Qom: Bidar. [In Arabic]
Sāwī, ‘Umar ibn Sahlān. 1337. Tabṣira (The insight). Edited by Muhammad Taqi Danishpazhuh. Tehran: University of Tehran. [In Arabic]
Subḥānī, Ja‘far. 1412. Ilāhiyyāt ‘alā huda al-kitāb wa-l-sunna wa-l-‘aql (Theology as guided by the Book and tradition and reason). Qom: Markaz al-‘Alami li-l-Dirasat al-Islami. [In Arabic]
Sabzawārī, Hādī. 1372. Sharḥ al-asmā’ al-ḥusnā (Exposition of the best names). Edited by Najafquli Habibi. Tehran: University of Tehran. [In Arabic]
Sabzawārī, Hādī. 1382. Commentary on Shawāhid al-rubūbiyya. Edited by Jalal al-Din Ashtiyani. Qom: Bustan Kitabl. [In Arabic]
Suyūrī Ḥillī, Fāḍil Miqdād. 1405. Irshād al-ṭālibīn ilā nahj al-mustarshidīn (Guidance of students to the path of the guided). Edited by Sayyid Mahdi Raja’i. Qom: Library of Ayatollah Mar‘ashi Najafi. [In Arabic]
Shīrāzī, Quṭb al-Dīn. 1369. Durrat al-tāj (The pearl of the crown). Edited by Sayyid Muhammad Mishkāt. Tehran: Hikmat. [In Arabic]
Ṭūsī, Naṣīr al-Dīn. 1361. Asās al-iqtibās (The ground for acquisition). Edited by Muhammad Taqi Mudarris Razavi. Tehran: University of Tehran. [In Persian]
Ṭūsī, Naṣīr al-Dīn. 1376. Sharḥ al-ishārāt wa-l-tanbīhāt (Exposition of remarks and admonitions). Tehran: Haydari. [In Arabic]
Fārābī. 1408. Al-manṭiqiyyāt (Logics). Part I. Edited by Muhammad Taqi Danishpazhuh. Qom: Library of Ayatollah Mar‘ashi Najafi. [In Arabic]
Kalāntarī, Abu-l-Qāsim. 1404. Maṭāriḥ al-anẓār (Conflicts of Opinions). Qom: Mu’assisa Al al-Bayt li-Ihya’ al-Turath. [In Arabic]
Lāhījī, ‘Abd al-Razzāq. 1372. Sarmāya īmān (Wealth of faith). Edited by Sadiq Larijani. Third edition. N.p.: Al-Zahra. [In Persian]
Lāhījī. 1383. Gawhar murād. Tehran: Sayih. [In Persian]
Muẓaffar, Muḥamamd Riḍā. N.d. Al-manṭiq (The logic). Najaf: Matba‘at al-Adab. [In Arabic]
Muẓaffar. 1410. Uṣūl al-fiqh (Principles of jurisprudence). Najaf: n.n. [In Arabic]